ARENA Working Papers
WP 00/26

 

 


The EU and Post-National Legitimacy



Erik Oddvar Eriksen* and John Erik Fossum**
ARENA, University of Oslo




Abstract

Much of the research on the legitimacy deficit of the EU is premised on the notion that pre-political elements such as a collective identity are needed to bring about social and political integration. A community-based sense of attachment provides the necessary basis for winners to compensate losers, and is required for majority voting to work. Save such elements, the prospects for wider European integration seem rather bleak. The deliberative perspective focuses on the manner in which integration is fostered by legal procedures and communicative processes between and among contestants, thus enhancing shared understanding and consent. The EU is a non-coercive and consent based system where unanimous voting procedures coincide with more complex procedures and processes to foster democratic legitimacy. The basic structure of the EU is derived from the structure of governance already in place in well-developed democratic states. The idea of the democratic Rechtsstaat yields the standards of assessment. However, the abstraction needed for legitimate post-national integration depends upon the institutional means whereby human beings are actually addressed as citizens of the larger political order.


Introduction

The EU has, within a remarkably short period of time, emerged into a far-reaching political entity, in territorial, functional, and legal terms. Its rapid growth and development has hardly been matched by a corresponding consensual understanding of what type of entity this is, nor how its democratic quality can be assessed. It is quite clear that its depth and breadth, and its ability to act along a number of important dimensions, are hard to comprehend if assessed merely by means of an `economic' notion of integration. This notion, however, is still the one that dominates assessments of the EU, whether such are performed by analysts or by decision-makers. The EU is conceived of as a functional organisation that offloads and relieves the nation state of difficult tasks. It is the performance of the system, its ability to procure service and solve problems for the Member States that are seen to provide the basis for its legitimacy. In other words, it is the results for the Member States that count, a view of present-day EU that is held by intergovernmentalists, economists and technocrats alike. In this regard neither democracy nor a common identity at the European level is required, as national democracy is the necessary source of legitimacy.

However, this kind of indirect legitimation is insufficient to account for present-day EU. This is so because it has become an entity that is more than a mere appendix to the Member States and that also has a far more profound effect on the Member States than for instance intergovernmentalists propound. Its impact on the citizens, the consumers, the workers, the clients, and the producers as well as the nation states is profound. Through measures aimed at redistribution, through regulation of social, environmental and health policies, and through police and judicial co-operation, the EU affects the daily lives of Englishmen, Germans, Belgians and Danes and increasingly central and Eastern Europeans, as well. The `direct effect' principle of EC law, premised on the notion of EC law as `higher' European law (that is measures within the first pillar) profoundly affects the Member States, and the European Court of Justice (ECJ) claims competence-competence.

The indirect or derivative model of legitimacy is premised on the Member State as a legitimate site of authority. The EU's broadened and deepened scope of action and closer and more direct links to the citizens of the Member States contribute to a massive transformation of the Member States. The democratic legitimacy of the Member States cannot be established independently of the EU, because the EU and the Member States have become so deeply enmeshed that the pattern of legitimate authority in the Member State is also transformed. The Member State can therefore no longer serve as the source of its own legitimacy, independently of the EU. [1]

The polity implications are clear. The EU is not an international regime nor is it an international organisation. It is a polity with distinct political goals and objectives. Further, the principles, organisational and institutional structures, and action programmes, associated with present-day EU, an entity that established the EMU and is currently involved in preparing for enlargement to the East, require direct legitimation. There was a time when it was perhaps correct to talk of indirect legitimacy but that time has passed. Now the legitimacy of the EU has to be based on something else and more than the democratic authority of the Member-States.

How can this be? How can the EU obtain democratic legitimacy? Can decision-makers expect respect for collective decisions, when the addressees of the law are so far removed from the authors of the law? There is no European demos and no genuine European-wide public sphere or truly European political parties. The absence of such entities, which are held to be basic requirements for democracy, makes the prospect for democracy at the European level rather bleak. However, not only institutional defects and the absence of a common identity, but what also may be seen as an overly restricted conception of democracy itself, produce such pessimistic outlooks. There are different ways of explaining integration – integration that is democratically realised and not merely enforced.

The intellectual positions that continue to dominate the research on integration, informed by instrumental and functional outlooks, hold that pre-political elements such as a collective identity, common evaluations and common interests, are needed to bring about social and political integration. Save such elements, the prospects for wider EU integration are seen as rather bleak. The discourse-theoretical or deliberative perspective on the other hand, focuses on the manner in which integration is fostered by legal procedures and communicative processes between and among contestants, so as to enhance shared understanding and consent. It is increasingly recognised that some of these elements are present in the EU and there is a need for a clearer understanding of what these are and how they affect and shape the integration process.

In this article we proceed by addressing the question of post-national legitimacy from a discourse theoretical point of view. Our point of departure is the strong connection between nation and democracy in mainstream political theory and the manner in which democracy is seen to rest on a set of pre-political values and the institutional makeup of homogenous nation states. This strong connection makes it all but impossible to comprehend already existing traits of post-national legitimacy in the EU. Is there any possibility at all for the EU to achieve popular legitimacy? First we briefly discuss some deficiencies in the prevailing perspectives on the question of the legitimacy of the EU. Then we clarify what is meant by post-national legitimacy. Thereafter, we discuss how well this conception applies to present-day EU. The emphasis is on procedural and structural aspects. In the final section, we present the EU as a fledgling non-coercive democratic system and argue that the onus on consensus is a precondition for legitimate governance in Europe.


Non-majoritarian sources of legitimacy

Instrumental and functional outlooks and their derivatives provide widely different conceptions of the EU, qua polity. [2] However, generally speaking, they share the notion that pre-political elements such as a collective identity, common evaluations and common interests, are needed to bring about social and political integration. Without binding norms or shared values societal co-operation can not come about and without such it is not possible to explain order as the result of co-operation between free and equal citizens. Functional interdependence and interest accommodation are inherently unstable, as actors will opt out of co-operation whenever they are faced with a better option. Interests make parties friends one day and enemies the next. [3] Therefore, an order cannot be reduced to the pursuit of self-interest or to the requirements of functional adaptation. [4] As interests generate unstable outcomes, extra-material elements - norms or values - are required to motivate collective action. Some must contribute more than they receive - some have to pay for the misfortune of others - in order to realise collective goods, i.e., goods that cannot be reserved for the ones who produce them. In principle, compliance with obligatory norms, which tell what is a right and just course of action, is required to resolve collective action problems and these can themselves not be reduced to optimisation: Social norms generally do not establish pareto-optimal solutions – they possess reality and autonomy. [5]

People, then, need to regard each other as neighbours or fellow countrymen, or brothers and sisters for solidarity and collective action to come about. Hence the search for non-majoritarian sources of legitimacy in the EU. Political integration does require a sense of belonging. A sense of solidarity and a common identification makes for patriotism or `love of country'. Albeit patriotism is not synonymous with nationalism, this type of political integration is held to be the achievement of the nation. The nation, due to its deeper ties of belonging and trust makes possible the transformation of a collection of disjunct individuals and groups into a collective capable of common action. [6] In addition, for democracy to prevail, such a collective must be made up of equals, as citizenship implies the ability to rule over one's equals and to be ruled in turn. [7]

A sense of community attachment - a we-feeling - provides the necessary basis for winners to compensate losers, and is required for majority voting to work. Majority rule is only a legitimate mechanism of governance when it rests upon approved territorial bounds and prior assumptions about the unit. One cannot hold a vote on who are the people, or who form the demos, because this is to presume the answer to the very question that is to be determined. The collectivity, for which the majority rule operates, must be decided by a prior choice. [8] This is exactly what is at stake in the EU, as there is no such collective identity and no common set of European values that provide a sense of community attachment and that can be readily drawn upon to settle grievances:

Representative institutions and parliamentary majority rule work well and provide for the democratic legitimatisation of government only under the condition that they are based on a collective identity called `the people' or `the nation', united by a common language, a common culture, common traditions. Such a 'collective identity' is lacking in Europe, and will be lacking for a long time to come. [9]

Should the EU then be seen merely as an intergovernmental body and not as an emerging political union, and as something different from the vision entrenched in the Treaties, that of a peoples' Europe?


Consensus democracy

The complex nature of the institutional arrangements within and across the Member States, the linguistic and cultural diversity of Europe, and the absence of a European wide community feeling strongly delimit the possibility of legitimate majority decisions on politically important issues. At present, at least, the resources required for collective action and redistribution are not available at the supra-national level. That is why for example, Fritz Scharpf opts for what he terms output-oriented legitimation. In this perspective the veto-power of all participants in intergovernmental relations makes for legitimation in itself, as parties will not consent to decisions that are contrary to their interests. Only decisions that no one will find unprofitable – pareto-optimal solutions – or that will make parties worse off if not accomplished will be produced, and hence lend legitimacy to international negotiations. [10] Scharpf opts for a position on the EU as having to rely on output-oriented legitimacy, which is government “for the people” not “by the people” and which is based on interest rather than on identity. [11] The EU then should be conceived of as merely a problem-solving agency which by itself and its outputs creates legitimacy: “What is required is no more than the perception of a range of common interests that is sufficiently broad and stable to justify institutional arrangements for collective action.” [12] It is the question of “... policy choices that can be justified in terms of consensual notions of the public interest.” [13] Several objections to this line of reasoning may be presented.

First, functional results themselves are in need of legitimation. As already noted, extra-material interests are required in order to co-ordinate action and solve the problem of collective action.

Second, in modern pluralistic societies it cannot be taken for granted that people agree on what these norms are; i.e., common interests, even a minimal set of material interests - a consensual notion of the public interest – can not be taken for granted. Since the early 1990s, in particular, the debate on the EU has been marked by dissatisfaction and opposition to the integration process and to the elitist and technocratic structure of governance. [14] There is a cry for more openness, transparency and participation. The debate on enlargement makes clear that there are many goals, needs, interests, entrenched rights and outcomes over which preferences differ. Then the idea of a prevailing common interest is at best illusionary, at worst technocratic, as this idea by itself will justify the absence of popular participation.

Third, negotiations are not merely bargaining processes in which given preferences and available resources determine the outcomes. A given outcome is not solely a stricken bargain between sectoral and partisan interests and dependent on the players' resources. It can also be the result of arguing. A lot of deliberation, negotiation, vindication and justification actually takes place in regulatory agencies such as committees, as well as in parliamentary and non-parliamentary sessions, and decision making bodies. [15] Negotiations in the Council are also markedly consensual. One survey of the Council revealed that only approximately “... one in four decisions are contested; only one in seven attract negative votes as distinct from only abstentions; only one in sixteen attract more than marginal opposition...”, although many of the topics dealt with were technical in nature. [16] Christopher Lord notes that “... resort to explicit majority voting is often viewed as something of a political failure” and what is more, the undertakings and procedures employed prior to decision-making indicate that the EU “... practises a kind of `extreme consensus democracy'”. [17]

Fourth, theoretically speaking, agreements may be of different kinds and of different qualities. An agreement may be merely enforced or it may be nothing more than a mere compromise, as we learn from bargaining theory - it is those controlling the most resources that win. [18] In these cases actors have different reasons for consenting. Another possibility is that decisions are made in accordance with a prevailing goal consensus, and without serious debate. Actors may justify their consent by appeal to tradition, necessity or pure opportunism. However, agreements may also be the result of a deliberative process in which the power of argument is decisive, which then ideally produces a qualified consensus. In this case, the contestants are not merely persuaded or led to accept a proposal but are convinced of its reasonableness and may defend it argumentatively in first person singular. They have identical or at least mutually acceptable reasons for their consent. [19] It is therefore necessary to distinguish between

- a compromise, which is the outcome of bargaining processes and which is only indirectly legitimated, i.e., through the procedures that set the terms of a fair contest;

- an actual or factual agreement that is produced by adherence to standard operating procedures, conventional norms and shared values, and is often understood as pragmatic or solely based on functionality;

- a consensus, which is the result of communicative rationality - contestants have reached an agreement by examining each other's standpoints in a reason giving process.

The latter is fundamental to democratic legitimacy, as it is, in principle, the result of deliberative processes where everybody has the opportunity to have his/her say. The rationale for this latter category of agreements is, first, that policy-making bodies contain not only rules governing bargaining and voting processes, but also rules and procedures that render deliberation possible. This also applies to the institutional and procedural system set up in the EU. It no doubt is a bargaining system. But the EU has also established procedures both for securing broad debates as well as for reaching consensus in institutional settings – in councils, committees, panels, etc. There is a clearly stated obligation to provide justifications and there are dense networks of communication, which help ensure such. [20] In addition, critical scrutiny, judicial review and openness [21] compel decision-makers to act according to acceptable – publicly justifiable - criteria. [22]

The second rationale for this category of agreements is that there is a need to clarify precisely which conditions of fairness, that bargaining and power relations presuppose and have to comply with, in order to claim legitimacy. Arguing helps clarify which kinds of agreements and common understandings on issues, goals and procedures that are necessary for log-rolling, bargaining, voting, and so forth to come about and to be deemed legitimate. A compromise must be justified and thus requires consensus-oriented arguing. The choice of these formal decision-making mechanisms must be argued for, [23] and this testifies to the more fundamental status of arguing as compared to bargaining and voting. It is thus necessary to take a closer look at the ways in which decisions are actually made - by whom and how, the mandates, procedures and constraints in place - in order to conclude positively on which mode of interaction is actually taking place. We cannot assume but need to establish through empirical research whether strategic bargaining (which intergovernmental and rational choice inspired approaches highlight) is actually taking place, and whether a consensus is presupposed or actually shaped in the process. These observations have important implications for how we conceive of the EU in polity terms and for the question of the EU's legitimacy.


Towards a supranational polity?

In order to understand the nature of the political system in the EU, in particular its democratic quality, it is necessary to supplement instrumental and functional outlooks, because these perspectives consider democratic legitimacy as largely irrelevant or, more interestingly, conceive of legitimacy in terms of problem-solving effectiveness only. Functionalism is problematic because the process of integration is seen as driven by spill-over: unintended consequences stabilise the system and make for legitimacy. Intergovernmentalism [24] sees actions as driven by self-interest - exogenous preferences – and it is the performance of the system that ensures its legitimacy. When goals are achieved efficiently and when the given interests or preferences of the Member States are satisfied, some sort of equilibrium is reached and legitimacy is produced. However, such equilibria are not easy to discover, as some states give much more than they receive. [25]

These perspectives on integration provide us with an incomplete theoretical basis for addressing the fundamental questions of order: What keeps the Union together? What are the integrative forces? Why does the EU evoke popular support at all? The problem of economic explanation relying on egoistic actors maximising their interests or preferences is that interest maximisation makes the social order unstable, hence “Hobbes' problem of order”. The problem is of how rational egoists can co-operate. [26] Without a central authority with the necessary (physical) means to enforce compliance, co-operation will not come about. Generally speaking, established theoretical frames of reference associated with instrumental modes of rationality appear incomplete to explain integration in non-hierarchical and non-coercive co-operative settings. No Member State is capable of dominating the EU. This is, briefly stated, the general background which warrants the quest for another theoretical frame of reference to guide the research on European integration.

Approaches to the EU that highlight its supranational features conceive of the process of polity formation, as something beyond the control of national governments. Most of the theoretical approaches acknowledge that the EU has supranational features, although they vary considerably in the assessment of the role and importance as well as emergence of such. Some perspectives, notably discourse theory but also new institutionalism in political science, [27] assert that the supranational character of the EU has to be explained by something else than Member State preferences and that the processes involved are not merely instrumental or functional. An explanation of the emergence of the EU as a supranational entity can not rely on the usual concept of state power, as the EU does not possess the required means, such as monopoly of violence and taxation and majority vote, to enforce its will. Neither its external nor its internal order is fixed. Reciprocity and mutuality are features that mark relationships in the EU. The voluntary and communicative aspects of the EU have to be brought to the fore in the analytical endeavour of explaining legitimacy in the EU. This calls attention to democracy as a legitimation principle because only the decision making process in itself can lend legitimacy to outcomes when values, shared norms, and collective identities are lacking. This forms the backdrop for the assumption that integration takes place through deliberation.


Integration through deliberation

The mainstream perspectives on the EU claim that integration may occur through strategic bargaining or through functional adaptation. These perspectives have placed inadequate emphasis on the role of deliberation in fostering integration. This is not akin to saying that mainstream accounts fail to acknowledge that there is deliberation in the EU system. [28] In specific examples this is acknowledged: “It is interesting to note that there is no general requirement to give reasons in the law of most Member States, so that these Community provisions [Article 190 of the Treaty of Rome and Articles 15 and 5 of the Treaty of Paris] were, and to some extent still are, not only different from, but in advance of, national laws.” [29] But if we are to account for the importance of deliberation in fostering integration as well as understand consent-based integration at all, we need a theoretical framework and attendant standards of assessment that can do precisely that. [30]

In democracies, only deliberation can get political results right as it entails the act of justifying the results to the people who are bound by them. Justification may take different forms. The concept of communicative rationality sheds light on speech acts, which involve actors attempting to achieve mutual understanding. Parties try to talk themselves into consensus by mutually respecting prevailing norms and validity claims. [31] By arguing in relation to inter-subjective, ideal standards of rightness, participants can reach agreement and an independent base for judging the reasonableness of choices. Arguing, then, is the procedure for redeeming validity claims. In other words, public deliberation that takes all interests and viewpoints into consideration is a way to find out what is just or fair.

In this perspective, rationality does not solely designate consistency or preference driven action based on calculus of success, nor merely norm-conformity or accordance with entrenched standards of appropriateness, but rather reason-giving: when criticised plans of action can be justified by explicating the relevant situation in a legitimate manner. [32] That is, communicative rationality designates the possibility of publicly defending a course of action. This is so even though appeals to moral norms in real discussions are liable to deception, the fact that parties at least are hypocrites – they have to pay homage to norms in order to achieve agreement – testifies to the importance of norms. [33]

Consent-based integration depends on the alteration, not merely the aggregation, of preferences. At least one of the contending parties must change his/her opinion in order to reach an agreement in a voluntary scheme of interaction. That is to say a scheme where no one is in the position to impose his/her will on others. Integration then may occur through deliberation, which turns on the process of giving reasons and examining the arguments that are put forward. Stability depends on learning and alteration of preferences in case of conflict, which in turn require reason giving including justification of action plans and impartial conflict resolution processes. In this regard we may talk of moral learning, as it is not solely based on experience, but on arguments of a certain quality, i.e., arguments pertaining to what is fair, in the public interest or promotes the common good. Deliberation, when properly conducted, ensures communicative processes where the force of the better argument sways people to harmonise their action plans. Participation in co-operative processes is supposed to contribute to such a shift as actors have to argue in relation to inter-subjective standards in order to obtain agreement, and which, hence, will override egoistic or national interest. In a free public debate, the moral point of view is forced upon the participants as everybody's interests are to be considered. Hence the norms of justice and fairness required to override national interests and bring about integration are produced. [34]

Before outlining this conception of democratic legitimacy at the supra-national level, it is necessary to question the prevailing view of a non-existing European collective identity due to cultural and linguistic heterogeneity, and differences in economic development and welfare standards, as well as in political-administrative arrangements.


Resources for integration

The history of Europe is often portrayed as that of conflict and disaster. Empires and states have been formed and complex schemes of co-operation at various levels have been devised. Conflicts and wars have unravelled all of these arrangements, at various times, and at various magnitudes. The two disastrous World Wars of the 20th century were certainly very important to the subsequent emergence of integration processes aimed at ensuring collective problem solving and conflict-resolution at the supranational level. This is not only reflected in symbols and proclamations - “this shall not happen again” - but also in commitments to collective political undertakings, made possible by what is after all also a common history. In other words, the history of Europe is more than that of conflicts and disasters. There are also historical factors that are conducive to the forming of a collective identity necessary for collective goal realisation and conflict resolution. Such collective experiences derive from a wide range of sources, which include ideas and ideologies, institutional structures and historical practices. Classical thought has had its bearing on this development and Christianity, the Renaissance, the Enlightenment, and the successive differentiation of value spheres of high modernity have contributed to a common European cultural substrate which also finds its institutionalised forms in binding legal and political forms. [35]

This process of differentiation was greatly facilitated by a vital aspect of the medieval notion of society, namely “that society is not defined in terms of its political organization.” [36] This and other social and political developments and institutional practices lent themselves well to the emergence of a civil society, which permitted the emergence of an economy as an extra-political reality and a public sphere where a public opinion could be formed outside of the state. Feudal relations of authority were also marked by a notion of vassalage that entailed a set of mutual - albeit not equal – obligations and from which the notion of subjective rights emerged. The contemporary development of a European transnational and rights-oriented civil society thus draws on political and social institutions and practices with deep historical roots.

The sources and forces of integration in Western Europe are not irreconcilable, they are rather “commensurable”, [37] due to the ethos of liberal democracy based on rule of law, basic rights and openness, i.e., a civic culture that is a pendant to the principle of rule of law. The cultural nexus of modernity is thus also reflected in the institutional complex of these societies, not only in a very similar economic system – market-based economy – and the competitive party-model of democracy, but also in a commitment to human rights and popular participation. As will be further developed below, European Member States are democratic Rechtsstaats, based on a liberal civic culture. However insufficient, weak and insecure such a culture, it has for several decades now stabilised the nation states and made possible democratic politics – including growing recognition of difference - and unprecedented welfare measures. [38] The nation wide sense of solidarity associated with the welfare state does depend on the willingness and the ability to abstract from local commitments to broader concerns, which turn on a successful change in identities and value orientations. Solidarity and democracy, not only capitalism and democracy have been the achievements of post-war Western Europe. These developments have not only changed the discourse in Western Europe so that war is highly unlikely as an option for solving emerging conflicts, but have also subjected the nation states to constraints that have shifted the parameters of power politics. The post-war emergence of new institutions – such as the ECJ and the EP – have reinforced the notion that law and democratic politics are the only remaining legitimate means of problem solving and conflict resolution, even at the international level.

In a larger, world-perspective the similarities and commonalties in Europe are striking when it comes to the basic normative infrastructure of political, judicatory and economic life. On these matters common language codes already exist. There has been a deep and encompassing European cultural intercourse for a long time. Today it has been expanded by new communication technologies, which together with higher education and heightened levels of knowledge in general have led to the rapid spread of new cultural ideas and of English as the second language in many European countries. English may soon actually achieve the status of the lingua franca in Northern Europe. [39]

Further, developments in communication technology such as TV and Internet, in addition to books and newspapers, constitute new public spheres and make transnational communication – in a transnational civil society - possible, to an unprecedented extent. [40] This is not to deny the problems of a weak collective identity, but to assert that the EU does also rely upon a common history of ideals and moral principles. No doubt this is the memory of disasters. But it is also that of greatness, including progressive political ideas. [41]

It should also be recalled that initially, at their time of formation, present-day nation states were forged by decisions that were often carried out by brute force. They were themselves generally not carefully constructed on the basis of a common memory or by means of popular discussion. As Charles Tilly has noted “(w)ar made the state and the state made war...”. [42] The historical experience reminds us that it is the successive democratisation of the nation state that has provided the glue that permits modern states to accommodate diversity in a non-repressive manner.

These observations suggest that there are other ways of addressing the problem of non-majoritarian sources of legitimacy than the ones stemming from primordial attachments or common cultural traditions and language. But is it necessary to presuppose the existence of certain shared values or virtues – in the sense of a collective cultural identity - in order for integration to come about?


Democracy and basic rights

There is a profound problem with the sociological or rather communitarian conception of the resources that are required to ensure integration in modern states. Such required resources, it is contended, include ready access to shared values and sense of belonging. Such a conceptual strategy cannot explain why complex and pluralist societies can at all hang together. Modern states may be stable and well functioning, yet they are highly differentiated, pluralistic and they contain multi-level structures of governance. There are many sorts of identities and belongings. When viewed in light of these facts the communitarian conception of order becomes confining. Multicultural societies display a heterogeneous value basis. Why these societies hang together may be explained, not by recourse to shared values but by means of a more complex model of how allegiances are formed. To do so it is necessary to distinguish between two kinds of social integration - cultural and political. The first denotes the kind of integration that is needed for individuals and groups who seek to find out who they are or would like to be. By this we think of the values and affiliations, language and history that form the glue of society - cohesion in general and trust and solidarity in particular - and which transform a collection of people into a group with a distinct identity, i.e., the cultural substrate of the nation. [43]

A distinction is required between the cultural or value basis of a political order, which is dependent upon a particular identity that prevails in the groups and nations of which people are members, and the constitutional order of such a society. The latter does not rest upon a particular set of values but on trans-cultural norms and universal principles. The constitutional order claims to be binding on all subjects and to be approved by the various groups within society, each with its particular and distinctive identity(ies) and value(s). Nation states are not merely �nation states�: as a rule they consist of many groups - social, ethnic, religious etc. - with different identities, values, and loyalties. Often, they are multi-cultural societies and as such require a second level of integration - political integration - which makes it possible to cope with difference and collective decision making without relapse into �ethnocentric politics�. Hence, respect for difference, pluralism, human rights, vulnerable identities, etc. is required. The basic structure of constitutional democracies, then, does not only express certain values or conceptions of the good society, but in addition a conception of a society based on the rule of law. Different groups continue to live together and resolve conflicts because they agree on the basic rules and procedures that claim to secure fair treatment of the parties. “Law is the only medium through which a “solidarity with strangers” can be secured in complex societies.” [44]

At the level of social interaction, the explanation is to be found in the way in which freedom, democracy, autonomy, equality, - in short, due process and equal respect for all - have obtained a deontological standing in our societies. They are principles, which it is a duty to comply with even though they could interfere with the values of the majority, particular conceptions of the good, roles, identities or utility calculations. That is why constitutional rights can function like trumps in collective decision-making. [45] Some norms claim categorical validity because they are derived from the inherent dignity of the person - they are so to say “... equal and inalienable rights of all the members of the human family ...” [46]. There is, then, not a conceptual link between ethnos and democracy, although there may be an empirical one.

It is in this manner we conceive of democracy and human rights, not solely as representative of cultural traditions and shared meanings, but as manifestations of cognitive-moral principles that command respect in and of themselves. They are essential prerequisites for self-governance and the cornerstone of modern constitutional arrangements. Constitutions protect the citizens' freedom by entrenching a host of individual rights. Basic civil rights cannot be altered by simple majority vote. Constitutionally entrenched rights clauses, in addition to the principle of a written constitution, the principle of separation of powers, and judicial review etc. impose restrictions on “the will of the people” and are meant to guarantee the freedom of the individual. They may be seen to protect the private autonomy of the citizens and are necessary for the formation of authentic private opinions. This thus provides for some of the “non-majoritarian” sources of legitimacy needed for collective decision-making.

Constitutional arrangements not only enable but also require and warrant popular participation in the political process. That is, they enable and warrant government by the people. The democratic principle entrenched in modern constitutions, refers to the manner in which citizens are involved in public deliberations, collective decision making and lawmaking through a set of rights and procedures, that range from freedom of speech and assembly to eligibility and voting rights. These political rights, and their attendant institutions and procedures may be seen as a way to secure the public autonomy of the individual. They ensure that the addressees of the law can also participate in the making of the law. However, modern states are large and pluralistic, and their complex institutional nexus, to function, presupposes representation and delegation of power as essential principles of governance. Voting, entrenched rights, representation and expertise should not be seen as “merely aggregative” as they also, under certain conditions, contribute to rationality and legitimacy. [47] The fundamental democratic requirement can thus not be everybody's participation in actual decision making processes, but the right of all to participate in deliberation on common affairs. [48] Democratic legitimacy does not stem from the predetermined wills of individuals, but from the process by which a common will is formed on the basis of the right that all have to participate in collective deliberation.

The criterion of democratic legitimacy is thus that the decisions that are taken can be seen as the outcomes of people's deliberation under free and equal conditions. Collective will formation does not require a set of shared values and opinions from the outset, but rather that all opinions are taken into consideration before a decision is reached, in order for democratic legitimacy to be achieved. The presupposition that a set of non-majoritarian resources, such as shared identity or common heritage and tradition, are required for integration to come about is thus less important. This is not to say that such identities may or may not prevail, as is captured in the notion of nation. This is not the core issue, however, as: “ ...this distinctive cultural identity does not designate it as a political community of citizens. For the democratic process is governed by universal principles of justice that are equally constitutive for every body of citizens. In short, the ideal procedure of deliberation and decision making presupposes as its bearer an association that agrees to regulate the conditions of its common life impartially.” [49] Democracy is thus conceived of at a more abstract level: it is not seen merely as an organisational principle – e.g. representative or parliamentary democracy – but as a legitimation principle which ensures the conditions necessary for justification. In other words, it is not identical with a particular organisational form, but is rather a principle, which sets down the conditions that are necessary for how to get things right in politics. Democracy is a way to form common opinions and collective wills about what to do but also to find out what is fair or just, and arguing is required for a norm to be seen as impartial in a political sphere of action. Modern democracy is thus not one among several alternative principles of associated life that may be chosen at will but entails the very idea of communal, civilised life itself . [50]

When framed in this manner, the basis for democracy is not a particular nation or Sittlichkeit - i.e., Kulturnation. Rather it is the norms and principles underlying the French revolution – the Enlightenment era – and which nowadays are spread well beyond the Western Hemisphere. These still constitute the most essential aspects of what may be termed `the European identity'. It is a genuine political identity that is based upon the principle of self-rule via the medium of law, and which entails equal rights for all, [51] but which also has to be supported by a liberal political culture of tolerance and pluralism in order to prosper. It may be seen as rather thin and fragile, as it is procedural rather than substantive, moral and judicial rather than ethical and cultural. But its fragile appearance should not delude us with regard to its appeal and strength. Its strength is derived from its appeal to universal cognitive principles of validity, and it is, and has for centuries, albeit imperfectly, been in operation in the democratic Rechtsstaat that was established at the national level.

Regarding the process of Europeanisation “... there is no call for defeatism, if one bears in mind that, in the nineteenth-century European states, national consciousness and social solidarity were only gradually produced, with the help of national historiography, mass communications, and universal conscription. If that artificial form of `solidarity amongst strangers' came about thanks to a historically momentous effort of abstraction from local, dynastic consciousness to a consciousness that was national democratic, then why should it be impossible to extend this learning process beyond national borders?”. [52] This perspective brings to the fore the democratic potential in the European integration process.


Post-national legitimacy

The analytical distinction between political and cultural integration referred to above is intrinsic to the notion of `post-national' democracy. The notion of post-national identity is that of a political identity which is founded on the recognition of democratic values and human rights, as these are embedded in a particular constitutional tradition. Citizens are seen as bound to each other not by those traditional pre-political ties that nation-states have appealed to but by subscription to democratic values and human rights. [53] This type of identity is conducive to the respect for and accommodation of difference and plurality. It is the constitution and the continuing voluntary recognition of the constitution that hold people together. In other words, what holds people together is their constitutional patriotism. An important question is whether or the extent to which this type of attachment can override primordial ones. Another question is whether the EU is in the process of adopting this mode of legitimation.

The EU was established as a type of interstate co-operation. But the EU has changed, and so has the international context. A purely voluntary, intergovernmental association of states does not give rise to collectively binding agreements as it is made up of autonomous states and based on the principle of balance of power. It is likely to run into problems such as those facing the League of Nations, which failed to authorise anyone to defend the shared principles. The process of reaching collectively binding decisions is, ultimately, legally dependent: post-national law must be made binding on Member States. The EU has clearly progressed beyond this initial stage of a purely voluntary association. It is an entity with strong supranational elements, as evidenced in the supranational character of the legal structure, which is supported and enhanced in particular by the European Court of Justice. In its rulings, it has long asserted the principles of supremacy and direct effect, principles, which have informed the actual operations of the EU, albeit their precise status in relation to national constitutional orders remains unclear. [54] Irrespective of the constitutional status of EU law, what is of particular interest is that supranationality does mean that the same obligations are conferred upon all, i.e., non-arbitrary norm enforcement. Law is a medium for stabilising behavioural expectations, because it connects non-compliance with sanctions. It solves the problem of collective action. Law enables moral behaviour as far as it is made binding on the parties and prohibits defection and free-riding: Actors may more easily act communicative rationally when the incentives for strategic action are taken away.

Further, the European Parliament which is directly elected by the peoples of the Member States, is also supranational, and has recently increased its powers vis-a-vis the European Commission. The Commission is the executor of Union policies and is endowed with the right of initiative, which includes the right to issue legislative proposals. The particular non-hierarchical nature of supranationality that marks the EU, is among other things, a result of its peculiar “separation of powers”, which ensures the Member States a strong and consistent say in the decision-making processes of the EU, and no single Member State is in the position to dominate the others. The institutional structure of the EU embodies a complex mixture of supranational, transnational, intergovernmental, and international elements. The structure in place in the EU is incomplete, in principled and substantive terms, due to its particular character qua polity, namely dynamism, openness and polycentricity. [55] This system is thus conducive to `non-hierarchical consensus' and `deliberative supranationalism'.

The EU institutions – albeit to various degrees – commit themselves to a post-national mode of legitimation. In the treaties, in policy papers and statements, and in speeches by central officials, they present as key a set of principles, which the `European project' has to be evaluated against. It is noteworthy that the principles and standards have undergone important changes in the last 15 years. The Maastricht Treaty represented the most important single change here in that the principles appealed to were not only universal in nature but were also far more explicitly tied to democracy as the principle of legitimation. These principles were further amplified in the process leading up to and in the Amsterdam Treaty itself. For instance, in the Report on the Amsterdam Treaty by the Institutional Committee of the EP, it was concluded that “the Amsterdam Treaty is a significant step forward for the European Union, compared to the Maastricht Treaty, in terms of democracy, freedom, the rule of law, social policy, solidarity and cohesion.” [56] These terms indicate that the evaluative standards, as expressed in official submissions to the process, have become more explicitly linked to democratic legitimacy, not foremost in substantive terms and as a particular institutional arrangement, but in procedural terms, i.e., as a principle of legitimation. Additional process-related standards, also closely associated with democracy as a principle of legitimation, were highlighted during the Amsterdam Treaty process. Particular onus was placed on

- the need for proximity to citizens (to counteract the sense of remoteness to citizens and people);

- the need for transparency (with regard to procedures and which is required to combat complexity and lack of procedural clarity);

- openness (which is needed to replace closedness and `cosy inwardness' and which refers both to procedures and to new entrants, and which was included in Article 1.4 of the Amsterdam Treaty);

- subsidiarity which was seen as a remedy against remote and centralized rule; and

- flexibility.

Other developments also reveal that there is a quest for popular support of the integration process.


Consent-based integration

There is considerable onus on consent-based legitimation in the very nature of EU decision-making, as already mentioned. This is apparent in the institutional structure and in the relations among the institutions. With regard to the institutional system, the main strength of “the dual character of the EU executive [is that it] facilitates extensive deliberation and compromise in the adoption and implementation of EU policies.” [57] Further, basically all the various decision-making procedures are based on extensive amounts of inter-institutional deliberation. The EU has also applied an unusual number and range of decision-making procedures, which probably makes it one of the most complex legislative systems in the world. Increased integration and a strengthened role of the EP have contributed to two important developments.

First, there has been a strong move from veto-based unanimity to decision-making through qualified majority. The latter requires more trust and hence trust that is brought about communicatively, as there is no far-reaching value consensus to draw on, and since the “permissive consensus” came to an end in the early 1990s.

Second, the number of procedures has been drastically reduced. The Amsterdam Treaty reduced the number of decision-making procedures to three: consultation, co-operation, and co-decision. However, it strengthened the role of that procedure which requires the greatest amount of deliberation and reason giving, namely co-decision. In most of the second and third pillars - i.e., in most aspects of the Common Foreign and Security Policy and Justice and Police Affairs Co-operation – the less arduous consultation procedure is employed.

The heightened role of the European Parliament in the EU's decision-making structure has led to more inter-institutional deliberation. The EP's decision-making powers have increased and its scope of action is widened, as it is now a co-legislator with the Council in thirty-seven different types of issues. Therefore, co-decision will increasingly be perceived as the standard procedure in legislative matters. Consultation or co-operation are likely to be considered more as exceptions. [58]

The onus on deliberation is evident in every stage of the decision-making process in the EU, as already mentioned. There is extensive consultation of affected interests, through lobbying and sounding out. In addition to committees of advisory and expert groups, the Commission, on an ad hoc basis is “committed to the equal treatment of all special interest groups, to ensure that every interested party, irrespective of size or financial backing, should not be denied the opportunity of being heard by the Commission”. [59] The Commission (and the EP) have taken active measures to broaden the range of interest groups directly involved at the EU level. The legitimacy of the EU partly derives from the deliberation that emanates from the non-hierarchical networks and webs of communication among actors who address substantive concerns and who are involved in the process of decision-making. This mode of interaction is very much the result of the process of integration itself. Although the initial setting up of a network can be seen as a result of conscious design, subsequent efforts are more the result of copying and adaptation, due to favourable results. Integration driven by deliberation, however, is not foremost a matter of an initial plan or motives, but refers to the process of reason-giving that is required when actors from different contexts - national, organisational and professional - come together to reach agreement on how to solve various types of issues. This mode of integration is premised on a search for valid arguments. Comitology committees represent one such example. The composition, interaction and outcomes of committees in themselves bear the burden of legitimation, not established hierarchies of one sort or the other. Comitology is in fact described as a new stage in the integration process. [60] As Joerges and Everson note

European committees cannot simply be classified as the agents of a bureaucratic revolution. Rather, with all its sensitivity for the modern complex of risk regulation and for the intricacies of internationalized governance within non-hierarchical and multi-level structures, the committee system may be argued to possess a normative, if underformed, character of its own; or, more precisely, to operate within a novel constitutional framework informed by the notion of `deliberative supranationalism.' [61]

Comitology does possess normative quality but actually how democratic it is remains to be demonstrated. Further, the principle of subsidiarity may contribute to legitimation through deliberation, as it places the burden of proof on the higher-level units. For instance, in its report on the TEU, the European Council and Council of the Union stated that: “The Commission has undertaken to justify each of its new proposals in the light of the subsidiarity principle. It makes more regular use of “Green Papers” and “White Papers”, prompting broad public debate, before new proposals are submitted.” [62] Subsidiarity prompts justification and polycentric views on adjudication. And whilst `Amsterdam Subsidiarity' (the principle of subsidiarity as entrenched in the Amsterdam Treaty) introduces more specific criteria for how to apply the principle, it does require the Community “to legislate in the weakest form necessary, leaving discretion to Member States.” [63]

The EU is formed in a manner that is quite different from how the nation state was initially formed. The modern nation state has its roots in a hierarchic structure of governance that was initially legitimated from above, i.e., with reference to religious and monarchic traditions and practices. The EU, on the other hand, is established by the Member States and is legitimated from below, as reflected in the central role of the Member States in its treaty making and decision-making procedures, as well as in central legal principles (legality and proportionality). Even the European Court of Justice, it should be noted, seeks to legitimate EU law with reference to its essential compatibility with the fundamental constitutional principles in the national constitutional orders of the Member States. The EU integration process is driven by the need to find solutions to pressing problems that no single state can resolve on its own. The EU is such structured that no single state can dominate the others. And the EU has very weak sanctioning abilities. It is a non-coercive consensus-based system and this affects its structure and operations.


Cheap talk or direct legitimacy?

The EU, as noted above, has a far-reaching direct impact on citizens and their affairs. It affects their interests in a profound manner, as consumers, producers, employees, and rights holders. The `direct effect' principle of EC law profoundly affects the Member States, and the Court has increasingly sought to justify “... its claims to judicial competence-competence as the authority interpreter of a `higher' European law by reference to the protection of basic human rights.” [64] The universal nature of this principle makes it one of the most potent reasons any entity can employ to support its claim for legal sovereignty. Also, the unity and sovereignty of the Member States are not left intact in the EU. However, the EU may contribute positively to Member State authority, insofar as the Union can serve as a means to handle externalities in an effective manner.

Due to its performance and the effects of the EU's policies, and in response to the democratic standards that the EU itself increasingly asserts, there is a rising call for measures to strengthen the direct legitimacy of the EU. This is underscored by many of the actions taken by the Member States to lift out decision-making: They use the EU to relieve the national agenda of difficult issues [65]. This highlights the autonomy of EU decision-making and liability to public accountability on its own. The EU itself claims popular approval - it claims to be a source of legitimacy in itself. Both the rhetoric of `bringing the Union ever closer to the people' - the Community as `a political union' - a polity - and the many referenda on treaty changes to increase the depth of European integration, are reminders that the power resides directly with the people. The European tradition supports a wide range of values, all of which are currently drawn upon to support the new European construction.

One may of course find these claims that the EU propounds as pretentious and as mere window-dressing, as do realists who generally conceive of ideas as information reducing means. But whether they are `really' intended as window-dressing or not, they may contribute to integration according to the civilising force of hypocrisy. That is, regardless of the actors' intentions, insofar as they appeal to norms that are widely accepted, they in fact confirm their validity. [66] These values are not only unavoidable as means of interpreting the history of the EU and as means of defining what it is about – its identity – but they constitute the very language codes for dealing with common affairs, such as the question of enlargement. Here democracy and human rights are employed directly as admission criteria, which applicants must adhere to, in order to obtain membership. In contra-factual terms, the basic norms and values justifying the EU may be forceful: Such principles spark criticism and are easily turned against the EU itself. They are powerful weapons in the hands of democrats. Cheap talk often strikes back.

The standards of legitimate governance – i.e., the principles of the democratic Rechtsstaat - that the EU appeals to and aspires to are becoming increasingly clear and apparent. It is however widely acknowledged that the EU is deficient in relation to these. The three most important deficiencies that are discussed in the literature are:

  • First, that the EU is inadequate with regard to its rights basis. This applies to the range of rights as well as the still ambivalent legal status of EU rights. Further, the fact that EU citizenship is still derived from national citizenship precludes the EU from adopting a uniform citizenship. It also means that non-nationals are excluded, and they have no recourse to appeals to the ECJ in case of violations. The pillar-structure of the treaties – with pillars two and three outside the legal framework - also acts as a constraint on rights development.
  • Second, the process of constitution making is closed, executive-driven, and technocratic. [67] Citizens have no assured way of knowing precisely which institutional practices the EU officials will adopt and how well these will correspond with the fundamental principles that the citizens embrace.
  • Third, the EP and the national parliaments are weak and inadequate as means of ensuring popular input and as means of holding the executive accountable. Although the EP has obtained the power of co-decision in the EU lawmaking process, its role in treaty making is marginal, which greatly limits popular inputs into the process. The weakness of the EP is compounded by the underdeveloped nature of intermediary bodies such as European parties and by the absence of a truly European public sphere.

However, something is happening in Europe.


Facing up to the challenges?

One important aspect of the EU's legitimacy deficit, which runs through all three dimensions listed above is the lack of popular support and sanction. [68] This has become more evident since the early 1990s, which saw the `end of the permissive consensus'. It is important to recognise, however, that the debate on the legitimacy deficit of the EU takes place within a setting marked by wide public support for binding European co-operation to ensure such universal values as peace, democracy and solidarity. The EU draws on and seeks to nurture this. In the most recent process of treaty change, during Amsterdam, the EU sought to locate the question of its legitimacy in such values as peace, democracy, freedom, human rights, the rule of law, social justice, solidarity, equality, non-discrimination, cohesion, security, efficiency, and cultural diversity. This suggests that the problem of the legitimacy deficit of the EU does not refer to the relevance or normative validity of the core principles that it appeals to as such, but rather to how these values are applied in practice. What has not yet emerged is a common understanding of how these values are to be institutionalised and put into practice in a supranational polity and this has become especially clear since the early 1990s. [69] This has sparked efforts – by analysts and EU officials alike – to try to establish a better coherence between the values and principles that are appealed to, and the nature and functioning of its institutional apparatus. These efforts cover all three dimensions of the legitimacy deficit of the EU.

With regard to the third deficit, that of the weakness of the parliamentary dimension, the EP has long pursued a struggle for public recognition which involves increased public accountability and efforts to strengthen its position vis-a-vis the Commission and the Council, and the Member State governments. This process is hard to understand, unless we employ the terminology and criteria associated with popular sovereignty. For instance, the conflict-ridden relationship between the Commission and the European Parliament, due to the absence of a clear-cut division of powers, has produced several important efforts to hammer out a more coherent and democratically based system of accountability. This effort was manifest in the Amsterdam Treaty process and it is widely held that the EP did obtain a strengthened role at Amsterdam. [70] It did not hesitate to fill and test this role. Consider the 1999 crisis: The Committee of Independent Experts was set up to report on various allegations and produced the report entitled Allegations regarding Fraud, Mismanagement, and Nepotism in the European Commission, and which lead to its dissolution and the reappointment of members, all amidst vociferous criticisms by the Parliament. The dissolution of the Commission in 1999 may signal a watershed change in the development of the EU, in that it promises to further increase the power of the Parliament and further enhance the supranational features of the EU, features based on strengthened and more well-developed conceptions of accountability, transparency, and honesty.

However, there are clear signs to indicate that a strengthened role of the EP does not automatically lead to more support, as was reflected in unusually low rates of voter turnout in the latest EP elections in Spring, 1999. [71] This low voter turnout is interesting, particularly given the significant efforts taken by the MEPs to heighten the status and role of the EP in relation to the Commission that year. One reason for this may relate to the weakly developed intermediary bodies such as truly European parties, and a European public sphere, which can serve to mobilise and convey public sentiments into the EU system. However, there are signs that a public sphere is emerging in Europe. For instance, it is difficult to think that the 1999 crisis could have come about had there not been widespread public criticism.

We see the emergence not of one uniform public sphere, but of numerous overlapping ones. What are emerging are networks of social and political actors, epistemic communities, and social movements, many of which emerge around particular issues and topics, such as corruption, BSE, and migration. These are deliberative issue communities, which transgress the bounds of language and nation. [72] New technologies and audio-visual spaces are also emerging - often market driven such as The Financial Times and The Economist. [73] Such communicative spaces are not restricted to economic issues, nor are they confined to the establishment of formal public sphere institutions such as Deutsche Welle, Euronews, and BBC world.

These changes in the institutional and societal patterns in Europe serve to underline that the EU is a polity marked by dynamism and poly-centricity. It is still in the making and is undergoing deep changes, in an almost continuous manner. Its incompleteness is reflected in its constitutional status, which is ambiguous and contested. [74] The key element here from a legitimacy point of view is not the legal status of the constitution but the principles and institutional arrangements that the constitutional structure will embody. It is widely acknowledged that the EU has established a constitution-type legal structure but it is incomplete and thus far lacks a clearly established telos. [75] This fact relates to the second deficit listed above, namely the closed and technocratic nature of constitution making. It is hard to see how such a telos can come about without an open and ongoing constitutional discussion.


Post-national democracy?

The EU is a post-national entity and appeals foremost to universal values. The applicability and salience of these values must be established in practice – and cannot be presupposed. Further, as noted, there is a very strong onus on consensus and the system is marked by a relative lack of coercive measures. All these factors deeply affect the nature of the constitution making process that is currently unfolding in the EU. Constitution making in the EU is not based on a constitutional convention or a particular and privileged constitutional moment. The constitution cannot be discerned directly from the treaties but emanates from the manner in which the EU's legal system is gradually becoming `constitutionalised'.

In the EU the conventional conception of constitution as a contractual arrangement that is established or given at a particular point in time is challenged. The lengthy and protracted process of constitution making that the EU has already undergone alerts us to an alternative notion of constitution making, i.e. of constitution making as permanent revolution. When viewed in this perspective, the constitution is not merely a contractual arrangement or a body of rules but also a set of procedures and rights that can accommodate an ongoing process of discursive validation of the structure in place. [76] In theoretical terms, this entails that constitution as a set of normative principles and justifications, and constitutionalisation as the process of discursive validation, are made to converge. It is this conception of constitution making that is compatible with post-national legitimacy.

The EU is in the midst of such a process of fusing constitution and constitutionalism. This process is coloured by an absence of ready-made justifications for the EU to draw upon in its search for legitimacy. The process of constitution making is far more than treaty negotiations. It is the sum total of the interpretations and rulings of the courts, the deliberations in the EP and the national parliaments, the deliberations in the various NGOs and public spheres in Europe and in non-European countries and movements. This process itself has to foster such justifications. The EU is a very dynamic entity and is still less a manifestation of a particular mode of governance than a meeting place where different interests, preferences, values, and identities come together. They may clash, compete, converge or cohere. But the structure provides considerable assurance that these can be heard.

The second deficit listed above underlines that this process has been far from open and all encompassing. However, there is evidence to suggest that the process has opened up with every effort to change the treaties. This is not foremost a matter of access in terms of direct participation. It is a matter of reason giving and justification and attentiveness to the views of those not formally part of the process. The strengthened role of the EP within the institutional system of the EU is one development that has contributed to open up the process of constitution making. The process increasingly includes strong publics, i.e. institutionalised deliberations “whose discourse encompasses both opinion formation and decision making.” [77] The IGC-96 also included weak publics, [78] where opinion formation and discourse are reserved for the general public. This applied for instance to NGOs and national publics involved in treaty and referenda debates. But an important challenge is to open up the process further to ensure that all those affected are heard, which also means that people are made cognisant of the processes and options and that the range of constitutional options is explored and assessed in open ongoing discourse. One option that is debated is to institute European-wide referenda, where every European citizen is invited to participate. [79] When the Danish and the Italian citizens are to address the same concerns, their awareness of the basic issues involved and at stake may be enhanced and a foundation for solidarity can be created. Provided the referenda are organised so as to encourage deliberation – through public debate, hearings, meetings and the media - rather than mere voting, the result can be to foster more common understandings. Other options to stimulate deliberation include a) measures to involve representative bodies such as the EP, national parliaments and regional representative bodies more directly in the process, and b) measures to activate intermediary bodies such as social movements and political parties. These measures would strengthen the role of both strong and weak publics.

The limited salience of weak publics in the process of constitution making is likely affected by the fact that EU citizens do not possess – in relation to the EU - the range of rights associated with and constitutive of the democratic constitutional state. [80] Citizens also do not have much direct input into many of the rights they obtain. The structure in place in the EU offers weak support for the mutual recognition and reciprocity that are such intrinsic features of rights and that are central for solidarity and justice to come about. There is a process afoot to rectify this deficiency, which is precisely oriented at the search for the normative telos of the integration process in Europe: Human rights and popular sovereignty. That this is underway is perhaps most clearly revealed in the decision to incorporate a Charter of Fundamental Rights into the new Treaty. [81] The decision to frame a Charter of Fundamental Rights was taken at the Cologne European Council (June 3-4 1999).

In October 1999, at the Tampere European Council, it was decided to establish a 62-member Convention (headed by Roman Herzog) to draft a Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union. [82] This is the first time that the EP is represented in the same manner as the Member State governments and the national parliaments in a decision of a constitutional nature. [83] The drafting of the Charter takes place in an open manner, in contrast to the IGC-2000 process, which is mainly conducted behind closed doors. The Convention consults with other organisations and on February 29 sent out an invitation for open hearings to representatives from civil society. [84] Since then hundreds of NGOs have submitted briefs to the Convention on different aspects of the Charter. These briefs can be accessed on the Internet. [85] On July 28, the Praesidium proposed a Draft Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union. [86] The intention is to have a draft prepared by October 2000 so that this can be dealt with at the December 2000 Summit in Nice.

The Draft Charter contains provisions on civil, political, social and economic rights. These are intended to ensure the dignity of the person, to safeguard essential freedoms, to provide a European citizenship, to ensure equality, to foster solidarity, and to provide for justice. The number and range of rights that are listed is comprehensive (a total of 48 articles). In addition to conventionally accepted provisions which most charters and bills of rights hold and which pertain to such rights and freedoms as the right to life, security, and dignity, there are numerous articles that seek to respond directly to contemporary issues and challenges. [87]

The proposed Charter must be read as one of if not the most explicit statement on the EU's commitment to direct legitimacy that has ever been produced in the EU. However, it is not without ambiguities and constraints. First, Article 49 provides that the Charter will “not establish any new power or task for the Community or the Union, or modify powers and tasks defined by the Treaties.” This provision raises questions as to the legal and constitutional status of the Charter, i.e. whether the provisions of the Charter are somehow subject to the provisions in the treaties and whether the actual contents of the Charter are thus automatically changed when the treaties are changed. If so, and since the Member States are `masters of the Treaties', this provision of the Charter could be seen as providing the Member States with a power to `override' the Charter. This issue of the legal status of the Charter will be settled in Nice in December. Some Member States, such as the UK, are known to want to restrict the Charter.

Second, the status of the Charter in relation to international and domestic Member State legal systems is not entirely clear. This ambiguity is exacerbated by the fact that all the 15 Member States of the EU have signed and have or are in the process of incorporating the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms into their domestic legal systems, whereas the EU has not signed it. Article 50, Section 3 reveals that the Draft Charter is intended to offer a higher level of protection than that provided by the European Convention. It states that “Insofar as this Charter contains rights which correspond to rights guaranteed by the Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, the meaning and scope of those rights shall be similar to those conferred on them by the said Convention unless this Charter affords greater or more extensive protection.” However, this issue is complicated by the fact that the Charter, in its present form, only applies to the “institutions and bodies of the Union” and only applies to the Member States “when they are implementing Union law.” [88] The fact that there is no constitutionally entrenched division of powers in the EU makes it hard to see what this distinction will entail in practice.

The Charter process represents a potentially very important development in the process of constitutionalising the EU. The result of the process will therefore tell us a lot about the status and future development of the EU, in practical and principled terms. This process of constitutionalisation is no doubt driven forward by the particular developments within the EU pertaining to closer integration, and given impetus by the particularly vexing challenge of enlargement. But it is also spurred on by the emerging global system of rights entrenched in the UN Convention and the European Convention of Human Rights. This development interacts with and reinforces the European Court of Justice's own embrace of constitutional principles and practices from the constitutional arrangements of the Member States. The net effect is a mutually reinforcing process of norm development – from above and `below' - which reinforces the conception of the EU as subject to basic democratic standards and requirements.


Conclusion

The type of legitimacy problem or deficit that we have identified in the above is quite different from that which concerns many analysts of a more cultural and substantive bent, ranging from communitarians to intergovernmentalists. In their assessment, the EU is faced with a profound legitimacy deficit because of the absence of a common tradition, culture and collective identity.

In this assessment, to place the onus on a common culture is to further complicate the process of ensuring democratic legitimacy. There are two reasons for this. The first refers to the question of diversity in Europe. The search for common cultural values and belongings may be a rather futile and even misleading undertaking. The problem is not pluralism and difference in Europe but rather the need for procedures to accommodate the complex structure of existing identities and plural evaluations, and to ensure that such are also fostered. This is an intrinsic normative feature of the liberal constitutional state. The wide extent of diversity is a resource for the emergent political order to draw on. In other words, despite Europe's religious, cultural, ethnic, national, regional, linguistic and other types of diversity, an order is in the process of being founded in Europe. Such an order is also not merely a result of a compromise or of an overlapping consensus, [89] but is rather the extension and the cultivation of a structure of governance already in place in well developed democratic states, i.e. states whose constitutions reflect the idea of popular sovereignty and human rights, and which are therefore founded on respect for difference. The integration process has reinforced the ability of the EU to influence and enforce democratic norms. The mutually reinforcing processes of democratisation – at the supranational level and in the Member States - have helped fuel this.

Second, however, institutional innovations have to be supported by altered opinions and identities in order to be successfully implemented. Identities are not merely prepolitical givens and formed by cultures but are also forged and fostered by political, legal and administrative institutions. Rights, laws and institutions associated with modernity are important in the shaping and fostering of civilised identities. [90] This also means that the type of deficit we address can be reduced by political action. After all, it is easier for the people of Europe to agree on common democratic standards and practices than to agree on a set of pre-political and cultural values that can be permitted somehow to stand beyond reproach. In this way also a European public sphere and a European demos may be created by institutional means. In the EU numerous organisations and a vast number of networks form publics. Obvious examples are NGOs, empistemic communities, comitology, European interparliamentary co-operation through COSAC and the EP. A supplementary option is to institute European-wide referenda. Opinion formation at the European level requires not only fora for debate, but also suitable issues to debate, and this in turn may over time foster the commonalties required for collective decision-making by means of majority voting. Thus, the abstraction needed for post-national integration to produce post-national legitimacy depends upon the institutional means whereby human beings are actually addressed as and see themselves as citizens of the larger political order.


References

Abromeit, Heidrun. 1998. Democracy in Europe. Oxford: Berghahn Books

Anderson, Perry. 1997. “The Europe to come”. In Gowan, Peter and Perry Anderson (eds.) 1997. The Question of Europe. London: Verso.

Archibugi, Daniele, David Held, and Martin K�hler (eds.) 1998. Re-imagining Political Community: Studies in Cosmopolitan Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press

Aristotle 1962: The Politics. London: Penguin.

Axelrod, Robert 1984. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books

Baier, Kurt. 1958. The Moral Point of View: A Rational Basis of Ethics. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

Beetham, David and Christopher Lord. 1998. Legitimacy and the EU. London: Longman.

Bellamy, Richard, and Dario Castiglione. 1998. “Between Cosmopolis and Community: Three Models of Rights and Democracy within the European Union”, In Daniele Archibugi, David Held and Martin K�hler (eds). Re-imagining Political Community. Cambridge: Polity Press.

Bessette, Joseph M. 1994. The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Bohman, James. 1996. Public Deliberation. Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.

Bohman, James and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann (eds.). 1997. Perpetual Peace. Essays on Kant's Cosmopolitan Ideal. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Bohman, James. 1998. “Survey Article: The Coming of Age of Deliberative Democracy” The Journal of Political Philosophy, 6(4):400-425.

Chambers, Simone. 1998. “Contract or Conversation? Theoretical Lessons from the Canadian Constitutional Crisis”, Politics and Society, 26(1):143-72.

Cohen, Joshua. and Charles Sabel. 1997. “Directly-Deliberative Polyarchy.” European Law Journal, 3(4):313-343.

Curtin, Deirdre. 1993. “The Constitutional Structure of the Union: A Europe of Bits and Pieces.” Common Market Law Review 30:17-69.

Dahl, Robert A. 1989. Democracy and Its Critics. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Dewey, John. 1927. The Public and Its Problems. London: George Allen & Unwin.

Durkheim, �mile. 1964. The Division of Labor in Society. New York: The Free Press.

Dworkin, Ronald. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. London: Duckworth.

Eder, Klaus. 2000. “Zur Transformation nationalstaatlicher �ffentlichkeit in Europa", Berl. Soziol. Heft. 2.:167-184.

Elias, Norbert. 1982. The Civilizing Process. Oxford: Blackwell

Elster, Jon. 1989. The Cement of Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Elster, Jon. 1995. “Strategic Uses of Argument.” In Kenneth J. Arrow et al. (eds.): Barriers to the Negotiated Resolution of Conflict. New York: Norton, 236-57.

Elster, Jon. (ed) 1998. Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Elster, Jon. 1998a. “Deliberation and Constitution Making.” In Jon Elster (ed.). Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Eriksen, Erik O. and Jarle Weig�rd. 1997. “Conceptualizing Politics: Strategic or Communicative Action.” Scandinavian Political Studies, 20(3):219-241.

Eriksen, Erik O. 1999. "Towards a Logic of Justification". In Morten Egeberg and Per �greid (eds.): Organizing Political Institutions. Oslo: Scandinavian University Press, 215-244.

Eriksen, Erik O. and John E. Fossum 2000. “The European Union and Post-national Legitimacy”. in Eriksen, Erik O. and John E. Fossum (eds.): Democracy in the European Union – Integration through Deliberation? London: Routledge.

Esping-Andersen, G�sta. 1990. The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism. Cambridge: Polity Press.

Estlund, David. 1997. “Beyond Fairness and Deliberation: The Epistemic Dimension of Democratic Authority.” In James Bohman and William Rehg (eds). Deliberative Democracy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

EU Draft Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union. 2000, CHARTE 4422/00

European Council and Council of the Union, 1995. “Report of 6 April on the Operation of the Treaty on European Union,” 5082/95.

European Parliament, Committee on Institutional Affairs. 1997. “Report on the Amsterdam Treaty”, CONF 4007/97-C4-0538/97 Strasbourg, 5 November 1997

EP, Press Release: 14-02-2000.

Fearon, James D. 1998. “Deliberation as Discussion.” In Jon Elster (ed). Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Fossum, John E. 2000. “Constitution-making in the European Union”, in Eriksen, Erik O. and John E. Fossum (eds.) 2000. Democracy in the European Union – Integration through Deliberation? London: Routledge.

Fraser, Nancy. 1992. “Rethinking the public sphere. A contribution to the critique of actually existing democracy.” In Craig Calhoun (ed.). Habermas and the Public Sphere, Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.

F�llesdal, Andreas. 2000. “Subsidiarity and Deliberation”, in Eriksen, Erik O. and John E. Fossum (eds.). Democracy in the European Union – Integration through Deliberation? London: Routledge.

Grimm, Dieter. 1995. "Does Europe need a Constitution?" European Law Journal 1, 3:282-302.

Gutmann, Amy. 1996. “Democracy, Philosophy and Justification.” In Seyla Benhabib (ed.). 1996. Democracy and Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Gutmann, Amy and Dennis E. Thompson. 1996. Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press.

Haas, Ernst B. 1958. The Uniting of Europe: Political, Social and Economic Forces 1950-57. London: Stevens and Sons.

Habermas, J�rgen. 1981/1984. The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 1. Boston: Beacon Press.

Habermas, J�rgen. 1996a. Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.

Habermas, J�rgen. 1996b. Die Einbeziehung des Anderen. Studien zur politischen Theorie. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

Habermas, J�rgen. 1998a. Die Postnationale Konstellation. Politische Essays. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

Habermas, J�rgen. 1998b. “Learning by Disaster? A Diagnostic Look back on the Short 20th Century”, Constellations, 5(3):305-320.

Habermas, J�rgen. 1999. “The European Nation-State and the Pressures of Globalization”, New Left Review 235, p. 46-59.

Hayes-Renshaw, Fiona and Helen Wallace. 1997. The Council of Ministers. London: Macmillan.

Hix, Simon and Christopher Lord. 1997. Political Parties in the European Union. London: Macmillan.

Hix, Simon 1999. The Political System of the European Union. London: Macmillan

Holmes, M. (ed.) 1996: The Eurosceptical Reader. London: MacMillan.

Howe, Paul. 1997. “Insiders and outsiders in a Community of Europeans: Reply.” Journal of Common Market Studies, 35(2):309-314.

Ingram, A. 1996: “Constitutional Patriotism.” Philosophy and Social Criticism, 22: 1-18.

Jachtenfuchs Markus, and Beate Kohler-Koch (eds.). 1996. Europ�ische Integration. Opladen: Leske & Budrich.

Joerges, Christian and J�rgen Neyer. 1997. “From Intergovernmental Bargaining to Deliberative Political Processes: The Constitutionalisation of Comitology.” European Law Journal, 3(3):274-300.

Joerges, Christian and Ellen Vos (eds.). 1999. EU Committees: Social Regulation, Law and Politics. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Joerges, Christian and Michelle Everson. 2000. “Challenging the Bureaucratic Challenge.” In Erik O. Eriksen and John E. Fossum. (eds.) Democracy in the European Union – Integration through Deliberation? London: Routledge.

Johnson, James. 1993. "Is Talk Really Cheap? Prompting Conversation Between Critical Theory and Rational Choice." American Political Science Review, 87:74 - 86.

Johnson, James. 1998: "Arguing for Deliberation: Some Skeptical Considerations." In Jon Elster (ed.). Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kant, Immanuel. 1785/1970. Political Writings. Edited by H. Reiss. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Keohane, Robert O. and Joseph S. Nye. 1977. Power and Interdependence - World Politics in Transition. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.

Keohane, Robert O. and Joseph S. Nye. 1987. “Power and Interdependence Revisited.” International Organization, 41(4):725-53.

Kratochwil, Friedrich V. 1991. Rules, Norms, and Decisions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Laqueur, Walter and Barry Rubin. 1990. The Human Rights Reader. New York: Meridien (revised edition).

Laursen, Johnny, Peter Nedergaard, Thorsten B. Olesen, Nikolaj Petersen, Mogens Rudiger, Tom Swienty, and Vibeke Sorensen. 1994. Danmark i Europa 1945-93. K�benhavn: Munksgaard.

Lord, Christopher. 1998. Democracy in the European Union. Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press.

Majone, Giandomenico. 1996. Regulating Europe. London: Routledge.

Majone, Giandomenico. 1998. “Europe's `Democratic Deficit': The Question of Standards”, European Law Journal, 4(1):5-28.

Manin, B. 1987: “On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation.” Political Theory, 15(3):338-368.

March, James G. and Johan P. Olsen. 1989. Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics. New York: Free Press.

March, James G. and Johan P. Olsen. 1995. Democratic Governance. New York: The Free Press.

March, James G. and Johan P. Olsen. 1998. “The Institutional Dynamics of International Political Orders.” International Organization, 52(4):943-969.

Marks, Gary, Fritz W. Scharpf, Phillippe C. Schmitter, and Wolfgang Streeck. 1996. Governance in the European Union. London: Sage.

Marks, Gary, Lisbeth Hooghe and K. Blank, 1996: “European Integration from the 1980s: State-centric vs. Multi-level Governance.” Journal of Common Market Studies, 34(3):341-78.
Miller, David. 1995. On Nationality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Moravcsik, Andrew. 1993. “A Liberal Intergovernmental Approach to the EC”, Journal of Common Market Studies, 31(4):473-524.

Moravcsik, Andrew. 1998. The Choice for Europe. London: UCL Press

Morgenthau, Hans J. 1985. Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace. Sixth Edition. New York: Alfred A. Knoph.

Nentwich, Michael and Albert Weale (eds.). 1998. Political Theory and the European Union: Legitimacy, Constitutional Choice and Citizenship. London: Routledge

Offe, Claus. 1998. "Demokratie und Wohlfarthsstaat: eine europeische Regimeform unter dem Stress der europeischen Integration." In Wolfgang Streeck (ed.) Internationale Wirtschaft, nationale Demokratie. Herausforderungen f�r die Demokratiteorie, Frankfurt and New York: Campus, 91-136.

Olson, Mancur. 1965. The Logic of Collective Action. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Pocock 1995: “The Ideal of Citizenship Since Classical Times”, in Ronald Beiner (ed.) Theorizing Citizenship. Albany: State University of New York Press, pp.29-52.

Pogge, Thomas W. 1997. "How to create Supra-national Institutions Democratically: Some Reflections on the European Union's Democratic Deficit." Journal of Political Philosophy, 5.163-82.

Preuss, Ulrich K. 1996. “Prospects of a Constitution for Europe.” Constellations, 3(2):209-224.

Preuss, Ulrich K. 1999. “The Relevance of the Concept of Citizenship for the Political and Constitutional Development of the EU,” Paper presented at ARENA Seminar, Oct. 1999.

Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

Renan, Ernest. 1882. Qu'est-ce qu'une Nation? Paris: Calmann-Levy.

Risse-Kappen, Thomas. 1996. “Exploring the Nature of the Beast: International Relations Theory and Comparative Policy Analysis Meet the European Union”, Journal of Common Market Studies, 34(1):53-80.

Risse, Thomas. 2000. Let's argue! Communicative Action in World Politics”, International Organization, 54(1):1-39.

Ryborg, Ole V. 1998: Det ut�nkelige nej ...! : historien om 6 m�neder, 9 dage og 17 timer, der rystede Europa. Information/Schultz

Schalz-Bruns, Rainer 1999. "Deliberative Supranationalismus: Demokratisches Regieren jenseits des Nationalstaates." In Zeitschrift f�r Internationale Beziehungen, 6 (2), pp.185-244.

Scharpf , Fritz. 1998. “Demokratie in der transnationalen Politik”, In Ulrich Beck (ed.). Politik der Globalisierung. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

Scharpf, Fritz. 1999a. Governing in Europe – effective and democratic? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Scharpf, Fritz. 1999b. “Legitimacy in the Multi-Actor European Polity”, In Morten Egeberg and Per L�greid (eds.). Organizing Political Institutions. Oslo: Scandinavian University Press.

Schelling, Thomas. C. 1960. The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Schlesinger, Philip and Deirdre Kevin. 2000. “Can the European Union become a sphere of publics?” In Erik O. Eriksen and John E. Fossum (eds.). Democracy in the European Union – Integration through Deliberation? London: Routledge.

Smith, Anthony D. 1995. Nations and Nationalism in a Global Era. Cambridge: Polity Press.

Smith, Dennis and Sue Wright (eds.). 1999. Whose Europe? The turn towards democracy. Oxford: Blackwell Taylor, C. 1995. Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Tilly, Charles (ed.). 1975. The Formation of National States in Western Europe. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Viehoff, Reinhold and Rien.T. Segers (eds.) 1999: Kultur Identit�t Europa. Frankfurt:Suhrkamp

Viroli, Maurizio. 1995. For Love of Country – An Essay on Patriotism and Nationalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Waltz, Kenneth. 1979. Theory of International Politics. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Weiler, Joseph H.H. 1999. The Constitution of Europe: "Do the New Clothes Have an Emperor?" and other essays on European integration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Wessels, Wolfgang. 1998. “Comitology: Fusion in Action. Politico-administrative Trends in the EU system.” Journal of European Public Policy, 5(2):209-34.

Z�rn, Michael. 2000. “Democratic Governance Beyond the Nation State: The EU and Other International Institutions." European Journal of International Relations, 6(2):183-221.


Footnotes

*e.o.eriksen@arena.uio.no

** j.e.fossum@arena.uio.no

[1] Cp. Beetham and Lord 1998,16.

[2] What we have in mind are first, intergovernmental and rational choice based perspectives; second, neo-functional, multi-level governance and other perspectives that rely on spill-over and by-product assumptions; and third, realist perspectives in general. For the first category of rational choice theorists see e.g., Scharpf 1998 and Moravcik 1998. For neo-functional theorists, see for instance Haas 1958. For multi-level governance theorists see Kohler-Koch and Jachtenfuchs 1996, Marks et.al. 1996a and 1996b. For the third category, see Morgenthau 1985, Waltz 1979. See also e.g. Keohane and Nye 1977, 1987 for particularly influential modified versions.

[3] Durkheim 1893/1964, 204.

[4] This is to say that such forms of collective action could theoretically be modeled as rational choices from the actors' point of view by means of game theory (tit-for-tat strategies and repetitive games) Axelrod 1984. However, these are `as if' explanations and seem highly speculative and unrealistic and quite often also cynical. On this see Eriksen and Weig�rd 1997, 225. For instance, the tendency to explain integration and enlargement as the mere results of side-payments, seems overly cynical, as it overlooks the force of justice in international affairs and of opinions about rectification of previously committed injustice in Europe.

[5] Elster 1989,151ff.

[6] Miller 1995. Mauricio Viroli notes that “The language of patriotism has been used over the centuries to strengthen or invoke love of the political institutions and the way of life that sustain the common liberty of a people, that is love of the republic; the language of nationalism was forged in late eighteenth-century Europe to defend or reinforce the cultural, linguistic, and ethnic oneness and homogeneity of a people.” Viroli 1995,1. See also the notion of `constitutional patriotism' later in this article.

[7] Cp. Preuss 1999,9. Cp. Aristotle 1962; Pocock 1995.

[8] See Dahl 1989,204 for a general statement and regarding the EU see Lord 1998,107 and Scharpf 1999a,8.

[9] Abromeit 1998,32. There are ”triple deficits ... lack of a pre-existing sense of collective identity, the lack of Europe-wide policy discourses, and the lack of Europe-wide institutional infrastructure that could assure the political accountability of office holders to a European constituency.” Scharpf 1999a,187. See also Scharpf 1999b,279, 1998

[10] Scharpf 1998,237.

[11] Scharpf 1999a, 6-12.

[12] Scharpf 1999a,11.

[13] Scharpf 1999a,188.

[14] Smith and Wright 1999.

[15] Hix and Lord 1997.

[16] Hayes-Renshaw and Wallace 1997,53.

[17] Lord 1998,47,78.

[18] Cp. Elster 1995, Schelling 1960.

[19] Habermas 1996a,166; Gutmann and Thompson 1996,53.

[20] Risse-Kappen 1996,68ff; Joerges and Vos 1999; Majone 1996.

[21] However, openness and deliberation do not necessarily eliminate egoistic motives, but force the actors to hide them and thereby actually confirm the validity of social norms. Elster 1998,110f.

[22] Findings from other settings support the role of arguing in the settling of normative priorities in political assemblies. See e.g. Elster 1998,97ff. For instance, close study of congressional debate in the USA has led to the identification of a series of informal norms that promoted deliberation. Bessette 1994,147ff.

[23] See Johnson 1993, 1998; Fearon 1998, see further Bohman 1996; Estlund 1997.

[24] Note that Moravcsik's notion of liberal intergovernmentalism is more sophisticated and somewhat less susceptible to this critique because it is an attempt to fuse elements of intergovernmentalism with liberal regime theory. Liberal intergovernmentalism, however, is based on the same micro-foundations as intergovernmentalism, namely the strategic rationality underlying the bargaining perspective. On liberal intergovernmentalism, see Moravcsik 1993, 1998.

[25] Consider in particular the role of Germany as a net contributor to the EU. For instance, in 1995 the German contribution was three times that of the second largest net contributor, the UK.

[26] Thus the theoretical problem of collective action, i.e., the propensity of being free-riders when enforced norm compliance is absent. Cf. Olson 1965.

[27] On the former see Joerges and Vos 1999; Habermas 1998a; Eriksen and Fossum 2000. On the latter see James March and Johan Olsen, for instance, who underline how preferences are shaped by actors' conceptions of institution-induced conceptions of appropriateness. March and Olsen 1989, 1995, 1998.

[28] See for instance Scharpf 1988, Hix and Lord 1997, Lord 1998, Hix 1999, who all notice the conspicuousness of consensus-building in the EU without, however, exploring its rationale with regard to the micro-foundations.

[29] Majone 1996,293.

[30] There is a growing body of literature that tries to do exactly that. See for instance Cohen and Sabel 1997, Eriksen 1999; Eriksen and Fossum 2000; Joerges and Vos 1999; Joerges and Neyer 1997; Kratochwil 1991;Risse-Kappen 1996; Schmalz-Bruns 1999,Risse 2000.

[31] Habermas 1984, 392.

[32] Habermas 1984, 15.

[33] Elster 1998a,100ff.

[34] Morality excludes egoism: By the moral point of view “we mean a point of view which furnishes a court of arbitration for conflicts of interests. Hence it cannot (logically) be identical with the point of view of self-interest. Hence, egoism is not the point of view of morality“ Baier 1958, 189-190.

[35] Cp. Smith 1995,130; Viehof and Segers 1999.

[36] Taylor 1995,210-24.

[37] This is extensively discussed by several authors, for more references see e.g. Lord 1998,119; Howe 1997,313; Smith 1995, Weiler 1999.

[38] However different the actual welfare state regimes appear to be in Europe. See Esping-Anderson 1990.

[39] Grimm 1995,295. According to the European Commissions's (2000) website “half of Europe is already multilingual”. However, there are big differences between countries.

[40] Archibugi, Held and K�hler 1998; Bohman and Lutz-Bachmann 1997.

[41] Renan 1882; Habermas 1998b; Anderson 1997.

[42] Tilly 1975,42. Lucien Pye sums up one of the most important findings of the seminal volume on The Formation of National States in Western Europe in the following manner: “Possibly most striking and disturbing is the finding of the authors of this volume that wars and the threats of war played such a critical part in building the strong states of Europe. The ominous phenomenon of war gave telling reality and unquestionable legitimacy to the reasons of state.” Pye in Tilly 1975,x.

[43] Grimm 1995; Habermas 1998a; Offe 1998.

[44] Habermas 1996b,1544.

[45] Dworkin 1977,xi.

[46] Cited from the Preamble of the United Nations International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights 1966. Laqueur and Rubin 1990,215.

[47] Bohman 1998,415.

[48] Manin 1987,352.

[49] Habermas, 1996a,306.

[50] Cp. Dewey 1927, Gutmann 1996.

[51] This is inspired by Kant who sees the state as a union of people under laws, and the constitutions and laws adhering to the principle of political right: “A constitution allowing the greatest possible human freedom in accordance with laws which ensure that the freedom of each can coexist with the freedom of all the others' .Kant 1785/1970:23.

[52] Habermas 1999,58.

[53] Habermas, 1996a,465f; Ingram 1996,2.

[54] This is evidenced for instance in rulings on the constitutionality of the Maastricht Treaty by the German Constitutional Court and the Danish High Court, both of which refused to grant EU law Kompetenz-Kompetenz.

[55] Preuss 1996,138.

[56] CONF 4007/97,15.

[57] Hix 1999,55.

[58] Nentwich and Weale 1998,8.

[59] Commission 1993b, cited in Nentwich 1998,131.

[60] Wessels 1998,1350.

[61] Joerges and Everson 2000,164.

[62] European Council and Council of the Union, 5082/95, 4. But see F�llesdal 2000 for limitations in the Amsterdam Treaty with regard to the principle of subsidiarity.

[63] F�llesdal 2000,88.

[64] Bellamy and Castiglione 1998,165.

[65] ”...the tendency of national governments to offload the odium for unpopular decisions onto the EU level only further exposes the character of its decision making and the nature of its authority to public questioning.” Beetham and Lord 1998, 14.

[66] See Elster 1998a, 111.

[67] For this discussion see Curtin 1993, Fossum 2000.

[68] There are significant variations among the member states with regard to the level of public support. For instance, Eurobarometer surveys reveal that although there are more people in Europe who feel they can rely on the national institutions than the EU institutions, the differences are not very substantial (34-38 percent for the EU institutions and 40 percent for the national ones). For these figures see Hix 1999,137.

[69] The initial Danish rejection of Maastricht was a rejection of central features of this treaty and not of European integration. According to opinion polls taken in 1992 where people were asked what they would vote in a possible referendum on Denmark's membership in EU (April and June) 62 and 68 percent of those asked wanted Denmark to remain part of the EU. Laursen et.al. 1994,270. Euro-Barometer data from 1992 corroborate this. ZA 2141/ICPSR 9847:209-12. The 5 largest popular movements that opted for a no to Maastricht wanted Denmark to remain part of the EU. Ryborg 1998,25.

[70] CONF 4007/97.

[71] Turnout rates varied considerably but were generally lower than in the 1994 elections. The national turnout rates were (1994/96 figures are listed in parenthesis) Austria:49% (68%); Belgium – compulsory – 95%(90.7%); Denmark 49.9% (52.9%); Finland 30.1% (1996:58%); France 47% (53.5%); Germany 45.2% (60.0%); Greece – compulsory - 70.1% (71.9%); Irish Republic 50.8% (37%); Italy 70.6% (74.8%); Luxembourg – compulsory – 90% (90%); Netherlands 29.9% (35.6%); Portugal 40.4% (40%); Sweden 38.3% (1996:41.6%); UK 24% (36.4%). Source:

[72] Eder 2000, Z�rn 2000.

[73] Schlesinger and Kevin 2000.

[74] Some analysts contend that it does not have a constitution. Others say it does but that there is a discrepancy between the structure in place and the arguments that are used to justify it, in other words that it has a constitution but not an attendant constitutionalism.

[75] Weiler 1999.

[76] Chambers 1998.

[77] Fraser 1992,134.

[78] For this term see also Fraser 1992.

[79] See Abromeit 1998,116ff on `the optional referendum' and Pogge 1997 on how a series of national referenda might improve democracy in the EU.

[80] In their contribution to the Charter process, the Platform of European Social NGOs and the European Trade Union Confederation (ETUC) observed that “(a) Charter which guarantees civil, social, economic, political and cultural rights will counter the apathy and scepticism which appears so prevalent. It is time to put ideals back into Europe.” CHARTE 4194/1/00REV 1, CONTRIB 75, April 28, 2000,3.

[81] : 'the Charter will add to the fundamental rights of Union citizens. By giving practical expression to the principles of humanism and democracy on which it is based, it must take on the force of a pre-eminent law which will guarantee, in all the Member States and applicant countries, respect for our shared values'. EP, Press Release: 14-02-2000.

[82] The Convention consists of (a) representatives of the Head of State or Government of the Member States, (b) one representative of the President of the European Commission, (c) sixteen members of the EP, and (d) thirty members of the Member State Parliaments (two from each of the Member States).

[83] See EP Press Service http://www.europarl.eu.int/dg3/charte_df/en/index.htm

[84] SN 1872/00.

[85] See http://www.europarl.eu.int/charter/civil/en/civil0.htm

[86] CHARTE 4422/00.

[87] For instance, there are provisions on `respect for private and family life' (Article 7), protection of personal data (Article 8), right to marry and right to found a family (Article 9), freedom of research (Article 13), right to eduation (Article 14), freedom to choose an occupation (Article 15), protection of children (Article 23). The Draft Charter also contains a Right to good administration, section 2 of which includes “the obligation of the administration to give reasons for its decisions.” The Draft Charter also contains several articles on non-discrimination and equality before the law. Article 21, section 1, states that “Any discrimination based on any ground such as sex, race, colour, ethnic or social origin, genetic features, language, religion or belief, political or any other opinion, membership of a national minority, property, birth, disability, age or sexual orientation shall be prohibited.” Section 2 contains a clause banning discrimination on grounds of nationality.

[88] Article 49, Section 1.

[89] Cp. Rawls 1993.

[90] Elias 1982, March and Olsen 1995.






[Date of publication in the ARENA Working Paper series: 15.01.1998]